- NOTICE -
(Cal. Civ. Code §18)
DISCLAIMER
I AM NOT AN ATTORNEY.
I DON'T WANT TO BE AN ATTORNEY.
I JUST WANT TO KNOW WHAT ATTORNEYS KNOW.
NONE OF WHAT FOLLOWS IS "LEGAL ADVICE", IN FACT IT'S NOT ADVICE AT
ALL. IT'S INFORMATION ABOUT LAW.
WHAT YOU DO WITH IT IS UP TO YOU.
FIND THE LAW LIBRARY AND VERIFY!
CONSTITUTION OF THE STATE OF CALIFORNIA
1849
We
the people of California, grateful to Almighty; God for our freedom: in
order to secure its blessings, do establish this Constitution.
Article I: Declaration
of Rights
Sec. 9.
Every
citizen may freely speak, write, and publish his sentiments on all
subjects, being responsible for the abuse of that right; and no law
shall be passed to restrain or abridge the liberty of speech or of the
press.
Sec. 10.
The
people shall have the right freely to assemble together, to consult for
the common good, to instruct their representatives, and to petition the
legislature for redress of grievances.

LAW OF TORTS
William L. Prosser
Professor of Law
Hastings College of Law
FOURTH EDITION
WEST PUBLISHING CO.
1971
Chapter 1
INTRODUCTION
p. 1
1.
FUNCTION OF THE LAW OF TORTS
A really satisfactory definition of a tort has yet
to be found. The numerous attempts which have been made to define
the term have succeeded only in achieving language so broad that it
includes other matters than torts, or else so narrow that it leaves out
some torts themselves. The word is derived from the Latin
"tortus" or "twisted". The metaphor is apparent: a tort is
conduct which is twisted, or crooked, not straight. "Tort"
is found in the French language, and was at one time in common use in
English as a general synonym for "wrong". Broadly speaking,
a tort is a civil wrong, other than breach of contract, for which the
court will provide a remedy in the forma of an action for
damages. This, of course, says nothing more than that a
tort is one kind of legal wrong, for which the law will give a
particular redress. But even this vague statement is
inaccurate in one respect, since one important form of remedy for a
tort is an injunction, granted in a court of equity, before any damage
occurs, while another is the restitution of what is been wrongfully
taken, and a still another is self-help by the injured party. But
the availability of all such remedies will depend in the first instance
upon the possibility that an action for damages would live for the
wrong thus averted, and so the statement made is sufficiently accurate
to serve the purpose.
It might be possible to define a tort by enumerating
the things that it is not. It is not crime, it is not
breach of contract, it is not necessarily concerned with property
rights or problems of government, but is the occupant of a large
residuary field remaining if these are taken out of the
law. But this again is illusory, and the conception of a
sort of legal garbage can to hold what can be put nowhere else is of no
help. In the first place, tort is a field which pervades
the entire law, and is so interlocked at every point with property,
contract and other accepted classifications that, as a student of law
soon discovers, the categories are quite arbitrary and there is no
virtue in them. In the second, there is a central theme, or
basis or idea, running through the cases of what are called torts,
which, while it is difficult to put into words, does distinguish them
in a greater or less degree from other types of cases.
Included under the head of torts are a miscellaneous
group of civil wrongs, ranging from simple, direct inferences with the
person, such as assault, battery and false imprisonment, or with
property, as in the case of trespasser conversion, up through various
forms of negligence, two disturbances of intangible interest, such as
those in good reputation, or commercial or social
advantage. These wrongs have little in common and appear at
first glance to be entirely unrelated to one another, except perhaps by
the accident of historical development; and it is not easy to discover
any general principle upon which they may all be based, unless it is
the obvious one that injuries are to be compensated, and antisocial
behavior is to be discouraged. This led Sir John Salmond,
one of the greatest writers on the subject, to contend as late as 1928
that there is no such thing as a law of torts, but only a law of
particular unconnected torts - that is, a set of pigeonholes, each
bearing a name, into which the act or omission of the defendant must be
fitted before the law will take cognizance of it and afford a remedy.
This view has been rejected by many other riders who
have felt that tort law is broader than any name categories, and that
some more or less vague general principles run through it, however
difficult they may be to formulate. There is no necessity
whatever that a tort must have a name. New and nameless
torts are being recognized constantly, and the progress of the common
law is marked by many cases of first impression, in which the court has
struck out boldly to create a new cause of action, where none had been
recognized before. The intentional infliction of mental
suffering, the obstruction of the plaintiff’s right to go where he
likes, the invasion of his right of privacy, the denial of his right to
vote, the conveyance of land to defeat a title, the infliction of
prenatal injuries, the alienation of the affections of a parent, and
injury to a man’s reputation by entering him in a rigged television
contest, to name only a few instances, could not be fitted into any
accepted classifications when they first arose, but nevertheless have
been held to be torts. The law of torts is anything but static, and the
limits of its development are never set. When it becomes clear that the
plaintiff’s interests are entitled to legal protection against conduct
of the defendant, the mere fact that the claim is novel will not of
itself operate as a bar to the remedy.
At the opposite extreme is the bold attempt to
reduce the entire law of torts to a single broad principle, that any
harm done to another is a wrong, and calls for redress, unless
“justification”for it can be shown. In its form such a
statement is objectionable, since there are some torts, such as
malicious prosecution, as to which proof of the absence of
justification is an indispensable part of the plaintiff’s case, and
others, such as libel or slander, where it is the defendant who must
justify his conduct, and lose if he does not. But even with
allowance made for the difficulty of wording it, the rule does not tell
us what the law will recognize as “harm” to another, or as
“justification” for it. There are many interferences with
the plaintiff’s interests, such as negligently causing him mere mental
suffering without physical consequences or depriving him of the benefit
of a contract, for which the law will give no remedy, although the
defendant has been clearly at fault. On the other hand, the
“justification” may be something quite different from the moral
exoneration which absolves the defendant in his own eyes and those of
his neighbors. Not only may a morally innocent man be held liable
for the damage he has done, but many a scoundrel has been guilty of
moral outrages, such as base in gratitude, without committing any
tort. It is legal justification which must be looked to:
the law will hold the defendant responsible for what the law regards as
unjustified - and so stated, the broad rule means little, or nothing.
Characteristics of a Tort
Abandoning the attempt to find a definition, which
“strictly speaking, is nothing but an abbreviation which user of the
term define may please himself,” efforts have been made to discover
certain characteristics common to all torts, which might throw some
light upon their nature. As is already been said, a wrong is called a
tort only if the harm which is resulted, or is about to result from it,
is capable of being compensated in an action at law for damages,
although other remedies may also be available. Beyond this,
it is been said that torts consist of the breach of duties fixed and
imposed upon the parties by the law itself, without regard to their
consent to assume them, or their efforts to evade them.
That is to say, that no man need enter into the obligation of a
contract with another saved by his own free will; but when he drives an
automobile down the street, the law imposes upon him an obligation to
all persons in the highway, to drive it with reasonable care for their
safety - and this without his consent or understanding, and if
necessary over his vigorous protest. If he does not do so,
and injures another, it is a tort.
But this, however superficially attractive it may
be, is an illusory distinction. All legal duties are of course imposed
by the law, and it is a modern rule that the maker of a contract is
held to assume the obligation, not because of his intention or consent
to do so, but because ally attaches such consequences to his manifested
conduct; and that he assumes it nevertheless when he has no intention
at all of doing so. Quasi-contractual duties are likewise
imposed by the law, without regard to the consent of the
defendant. In the same sense, the tort duty of care and
driving the cars assume because ally attaches that result to what is
been done voluntarily. Furthermore, such tort obligations
of conduct are imposed by reason of the relation in which a party stand
toward one another; and in determining that relation, the law will
often take into account what is been agreed between them, either to
increase the actors responsibility or to lessen it, so that the tort
duty finally fixed may coincide with that set by a contract, or for its
breach either a contract or at tort action will lie. To say
that the one obligation is voluntarily assumed in such a case, while he
other is not, is to resort to abstract fictions.
Again, it is been said that tort duties are owed to
persons generally, or toward general classes of persons. Or
in other words, that the automobile driver is under a tort obligation
of care to everyone in his path whom he may injure, and is not free, as
he is when he makes contract or accepts a trust, to single out one
person only toward whom he will be bound. Certainly the
distinction holds good in many cases: a common carrier, for example,
may make a different contract with each single passenger, varying in
its terms as to fair and the length of transportation, but the tort
duty of reasonable care for their safety extends to every person toward
whom stands in the relation of carrier and passenger, including those
who have not contracted at all, but are riding free.
p. 7
2.
TORT AND CRIME
A tort is not the same thing as a crime, although
the two sometimes have many of the same features in common.
The distinction between them lies in the interest affected and the
remedy afforded by the law. A crime is an offense against the
public at large, for which the state, as the representative of the
public, will bring proceeding in the form of a criminal
prosecution. The purpose of such a proceeding is to protect
and vindicate the interests of the public as a whole, by punishing the
offender or eliminating him from society, either permanently or for a
limited time, by reforming him or teaching him not to repeat the
offense, and by deterring others from imitating him. A
criminal prosecution is not concerned in any way with the compensation
of the injured individual against whom the crime is committed, and his
only part in it is that of an accuser and a witness for the
state. So far as the criminal law is concerned, he will
leave the courtroom empty-handed.
The civil
action for a tort, on the other hand, is commenced and maintained by
the injured person himself, and its purpose is to compensate him for
the damage he has suffered, at the expense of the
wrongdoer. If he is successful, he receives a judgement for
a sum of money, which he may enforce by collecting it from the
defendant.
Chapter
2
INTENTIONAL INTERFERENCE WITH
THE PERSON
ASSAULT
p. 40 - 41
Intent
To be held liable for assault,
the defendant must have intended to interfere with the plaintiff's
personal integrity - which is to say that he must have intended to
bring about an assault, a battery, or an imprisonment.
There is, properly speaking, no such thin as a negligent
assault. But the intent need not necessarily be to inflict
physical injury, and it is enough that there is an intent to arouse
apprehension. Thus it is an assault to fire a gun not aimed
at the plaintiff for the purpose of frightening him, or to point it at
him when the defendant knows that is it unloaded, and the plaintiff
does not. "It is not the secret intent of the assaulting
party, nor the undisclosed fact of his ability or inability to commit a
battery that is material; but what his conduct and the attending
circumstances denote at the time to the party assaulted. Once the
apprehension has been intentionally created, it is no defense that the
defendant changed his mind, and desisted or withdrew without doing
physical harm. The tort is complete with the invasion of
the plaintiff's mental peace, and the failure to carry it through to
batter will not prevent liability.
Assault and Battery
Assault and battery go together
like ham and eggs. The difference between them is that
between physical contact and the mere apprehension of it.
One may exist without the other. It is a battery to strike
a man while he is asleep, although he does not discover it until
afterward; it is an assault to shoo at him, frighten him and miss
him. Except for this difference in the character of the
invasion of the plaintiff's interests, the two are in all respects
identical, and there is no apparent reason why the rules applied to
battery, including the fiction of "transferred intent", should not also
apply to assault. In the ordinary case, both assault and
battery are present; it is an assault when the defendant seings his
fist to strike the plaintiff, and the plaintiff sees the movement, a
battery when the fist comes in contact with the plaintiff's nose.
The two terms are so closely associated in common usage that they are
generally used together, or regarded as more or less
synonymous. Loosely drawn criminal statutes, which make use
of "assault" to include attempted battery itself, have assisted in the
obscuring the distinction. It is not accurate to say that
every battery includes and assault," but in practice the difference
between the two is often entirely ignored.
Chapter
4
DEFENSES TO INTENTIONAL INTERFERENCE
WITH PERSON OR PROPERTY
p. 131 - 133
26.
ARREST WITHOUT A WARRANT
The details of the complex rules which have grown up
around arrest a warrant might better be considered in a treatise on
criminal law. A distinction necessarily has been made
between the authority of officers of the law, charged with the official
duty of enforcing it, and that of private citizens. The
power to arrest has been limited according to the gravity of the crime
with which the wrongdoer is to be charged. Highly technical
distinctions have been drawn between felonies, which in general are
major crimes; breaches of the peace which are public offenses done by
violence, or likely to create public disturbance; and the greater
number of minor criminal violations which are mere
misdemeanors. The classification of a particular
offense is very largely a matter of statute, and will vary in each
jurisdiction. The unfortunate officer or citizen is
required to know these distinctions, or to act at his peril.
Broadly speaking, either an officer or a private
citizen may arrest without a warrant to prevent a felony or a breach of
the peace which being committed, or reasonably appears about to be
committed, in his presence. Once the crime has been
committed, the jealous safeguards which the law always has thrown about
the personal liberty of the individual have led to a restriction of the
privilege. The officer, representing the state, may still
arrest without legal process if he has information which affords a
reasonable ground for suspicion that a felony has been committed, and
that he has the right criminal. The burden rests upon him
to show that he has reasonable grounds, and mere suspicion, unsupported
by information, is not enough. The private person may
arrest in a felony has in fact been committed, and he has reasonable
grounds to suspect the man whom he arrests, but his authority depend
upon the fact of the crime, and he must take the full risk that none
has been committed. A reasonable mistake as to the
individual will protect him, but a mistake as to the felony will
not.
The person
arrested must be informed of the charges against him, and an arrest
made upon an improper ground cannot later be justified because there
was a proper one available.
Chapter 5
NEGLIGENCE: STANDARD OF CONDUCT
28. HISTORY
Negligence was scarcely recognized as a separate tort before the
earlier part of the 19th century. Prior to that time the
word had been used in a very general sense to describe the breach of
any legal obligation, or to designate a mental element, usually one of
inadvertence or indifference, entering into the commission of other
torts. Some writers, in fact, once maintained that
negligence was merely one way of committing any other tort, and itself
had no particular legal significance, just as some courts, for example,
still speak occasionally of a negligent “battery.” But for
more than a century, it has received more or less general recognition
as an independent basis of liability, with distinct features of its
own, differing on the one hand from the intentional torts and on the
other from those in which strict liability is imposed.
One of the earliest appearances of what we now know as negligence was
in the liability of those who profess to be competent in certain
“public” callings. A carrier, and innkeeper, a blacksmith,
or a surgeon, was regarded as holding himself out to the public as one
in whom confidence might be reposed, and hence as assuming an
obligation to give proper service, for the breach of which, by any
negligent conduct, he might be liable but in the field of trespass and
nuisance, the notion also developed, thinly disguised, that there might
be liability for negligence; and in later years, the action on the case
produced a large, undigested group of situations in which negligence
was the essence of the tort. Since the early law found its hands
full in dealing with the more outrageous forms of misbehavior, it was
natural that the early cases should be concerned almost exclusively
with positive acts, rather than with omissions to act, or with
“misfeasance” rather than “nonfeasance.” There was a slow
development of the idea that certain relations between the parties
might impose an obligation to take affirmative action, so that there
might be liability for nonfeasance. Any such obligation
remains to this day very largely a matter of some specific relation, by
reason of which the defendant may be regarded as having undertaken a
duty to act. New paragraph about the year 1825, negligence
began to be recognized as a separate and independent basis of tort
liability. It’s rise coincided in a marked degree with the
Industrial Revolution; and it very probably was stimulated by the rapid
increase in the number of accidents caused by industrial machinery, and
in particular by the invention of railways. It undoubtedly
was greatly encouraged by the disintegration of the old forms of
action, and the disappearance of the distinction between direct and
indirect injuries, found in trespass and case. The
cause of action which at least emerge from this process of reshuffling
took on, in general, the aspects of the action on the case, largely
because the facts upon which the initial decisions were based fitted
that action intentional injuries, whether direct or indirect, began to
be grouped as a distinct field of liability, and negligence remained as
the main basis for unintended torts. Today it is not at all
disputed that separate problems and principles, as well as distinct
questions of policy, a rise in negligence cases.
29. UNAVOIDABLE ACCIDENT
In unavoidable accident is an occurrence which was not intended, and
which, under all the circumstances, could not have been foreseen or
prevented by the exercise of reasonable precautions. No
accident, of course is entirely inevitable, so long as a results from
any voluntary act. If the defendant rides a horse, which
runs away with him and injures the plaintiff, the accident is not
strictly inevitable, since the defendant intentionally rode the horse,
and might have prevented all harm by keeping him in the
barn. But the runaway is called “unavoidable” if it did not
result from any lack of proper care in the management of the horse,
because both wrongful intent and negligence are lacking.
There is no liability in such a case. Upon exactly the same
basis, the driver of an automobile who suddenly loses control of his
car because he is seized with a heart attack, stroke, a fainting spell,
or epileptic fit, or is merely overcome by slumber, is not liable
unless he knew that he was likely to become ill or go to sleep, in
which case he is found to be negligent in driving the car at
all. The same conclusions are reached when the defendant’s
car struck by another vehicle and thrown out of control, or a child and
foreseeably dashes out in front of the car such rules are adopted
because the line must. Be drawn somewhere and if the defendant is to be
held liable merely because he has ridden a horse or driven the car, it
would be quite as logical, at least in the eyes of the law, to hold him
liable for owning it, or even for drawing his breath or being
born. To hold that he does every voluntary act at his
peril, and must ensure others against all of the consequences that may
occur, would be an entirely unreasonable and quite intolerable burden
upon all of human activity.
Nevertheless, as to injuries to persons or property which followed as
the more direct and immediate consequence of voluntary act, and for
which an action of trespass would lie, the early common law imposed a
very strict responsibility. The defendant who fired a
gun, and accidentally wounded the plaintiff, was held liable unless he
could establish that the accident was in evitable - “judged utterly
without his fault; as if a man by force take my hand and strike you -“
and the burden was upon him to prove that such was the
case. As has been stated above, the progress of the law has
been away from this position. There were jurisdictions in
which the rule survived well into the 19th century, that if the
defendant voluntarily discharged the gun, he was liable for the
injury. But in Brown versus Kendall, where the defendant,
interfering in a dogfight, raised his stick and accidentally struck a
man behind them, the Massachusetts court held that there was no
liability in the absence of some wrongful intent or
negligence. This case is now uniformly
followed. The man who fires a gun, the automobile driver
whose tire blows out, the boy on a bicycle who frightens a horse, the
man who instinctively and reasonably seizes another to save himself
from falling, are responsible for the damage done only if they have
been at fault; and by the great weight of authority, the burden of
proof of such fault is upon the plaintiff.
There is been some vestiges of the older rule which have died
hard. Strict liability for unavoidable accident still
appears in one or two states, as a more or less antiquated survival, in
trespass to land, where the trespasser is held liable not only for any
accidental damage he may do in the course of his trespass, but for an
accidental trespass itself. It appears also in the
case of the keeping of dangerous animals and other abnormally dangerous
activities, where considerations of policy have been found to support
it in a few states, it has been said in gunshot cases that the burden
is upon the defendant to show that he was free from negligence; but it
is not clear that these cases mean to say that there is sufficient
evidence of negligence in the occurrence of the accident itself to make
out a prima facia case.
In
England, the rule survived until 1959, when it was finally laid to
rest, that where the injury to the plaintiff was direct and immediate,
so that the ancient action of trespass would have lain, the defendant
had the burden of proving that he was not negligent.
One form in which the older rule sometimes still appears is a statement
found occasionally, that if the act itself was “unlawful,” the actor is
liable for all accidental consequences. Upon this basis, a
defendant hunting on Sunday in violation of the statute was once held
liable for shooting a companion by pure accident, and one beating a
horse was held for an injury to a man. Under modern law,
such a principle is certainly far too broad, except as it may perhaps
have reference to the doctrine of “transferred intent,” or perhaps to
certain situations involving negligence. The conception of
absolute fault, extending to all unavoidable consequences, is not
workable in modern society; “with the increasing catalog of unlawful
acts, it cannot be followed through.” If the “unlawfulness”
of the act consists merely in the violation of a statute designed to
protect the interests of the state, or the public at large, against an
entirely different kind of harm - as in the case of the Sunday statute
- there is no liability for results which could not have been avoided
by reasonable care in the act itself.
30. ELEMENTS OF CAUSE OF ACTION
Negligence,
as we shall see, is simply one kind of conduct. But a cause
of action founded upon negligence, from which liability will follow,
requires more than conduct. The traditional formula for the
elements necessary to such a cause of action may be stated briefly as
follows:
1. A
duty, or obligation, recognized by the law, requiring the actor to
conform to a certain standard of conduct, for the protection of others
against unreasonable risk.
2. A
failure on his part to conform to the standard required.
These two elements go to make up what the court usually have called
negligence; but the term quite frequently is applied to the second
alone. Thus it may be said that the defendant was
negligent, but is not liable because he was under no duty to the
plaintiff not to be.
3. A
reasonable close causal connection between the conduct and the
resulting injury. This is what is commonly known as “legal cause,” or
“proximate cause.”
4. Actual
loss or damage resulting to the interests of another. Since
the action for negligence developed chiefly out of the old form of
action on the case, it retained the rule that action, that proof of
damage was an essential part of the plaintiff’s case.
Nominal damages, to vindicate a technical right, cannot be recovered in
a negligence action, were no actual loss has occurred. The
threat of future harm, not yet realized, is not enough.
Negligent conduct in itself is not such an interference with the
interests of the world at large that there is any right to complain of
it, or to be free from it, except in the case of some individual whose
interests have suffered.
Such a statement must, however, be qualified to the extent that as in
the case of other torts, where the repairable injuries threaten, a
court of equity may act by injunction to prevent the harm before it
occurs. Even here the damage, even though only potential,
is the basis for granting relief.
It follows that the statute of limitations does not begin to run
against a negligence action until some damage has occurred.
This has led to real difficulties where, as is frequently the case in
actions for medical malpractice, the statute has run before the
plaintiff discovers that he has suffered any injury at all.
The older approach to such cases was a literal application of the
statute to bar the action, regarding it as intended to protect the
defendant not only against fictitious claims, but also against the
difficulty of obtaining evidence after lapse of time even when he is
confronted with a genuine one; and considering the hardship upon the
plaintiff as merely part of the price to be paid for such
protection. The obvious and flagrant injustice of such
cases has led to the adoption of a series of transparent devices to get
around the rule. Thus the negligent treatment or at least
the defendant’s duty, is held to continue until the relation of
physician and patient has ended; or the court finds fraudulent
concealment of the damage, which holds the running of the statute; or
it finds “constructive” fraud in silence with probable knowledge; or
the failure to discover and remove the sponge or other foreign object
left in the plaintiff’s body is held to be “continuing”
negligence. Quite recently there a been a wave of decisions
meeting the issue head on, and holding that the statue will no longer
be construed as intended to run until the plaintiff has in fact
discovered that he has suffered injury, or by the exercise of
reasonable diligence should have discovered it. While there
will undoubtedly be cases in which this will result in shifting the
hardship which must be borne by someone to the defendant, it has been
said that “if, as is to be hoped, the resulting jeopardy to defendants
produces a greater measure of caring connection with surgical
operations, so much the better.”
There are already a sprinkling of cases in which this “discovery” rule
has been applied to other professional negligence, such as that of an
accountant or architect, or even to damage to an adjoining land owner.
31. UNREASONABLE RISK
Negligence is a matter of risk - that is to say, of
recognizable danger of injury. It is been defined as
“conduct which involves an unreasonably great risk of causing damage,”
or, more fully, conduct “which falls below the standard established by
law for the protection of others against unreasonably great risk of
harm.” “Negligence is conduct, and not a state of
mind.” In most instances, it is caused by heedlessness or
carelessness, which makes the negligent party unaware of the results
which may follow from his act. But it may also exist where
h has considered the possible consequences carefully, and his exercises
own best judgment. The standard imposed by society is
an external one, which is not necessarily based upon any moral fault of
the individual; and a failure to conform to it is negligence, even
though it may be due to stupidity, forgetfulness, and excitable
temperament, or even sheer ignorance. The almost
universal use of the phrase “due care” to describe conduct which is not
negligent, should not be permitted to obscure the fact that the real
basis of negligence is not carelessness, but behavior which should be
recognized as involving unreasonable danger to others.
Previous reference has been made to the distinction
between negligence and intent. In negligence, the actor does not desire
to bring about the consequences which follow, nor does he know that
they are substantially certain to occur, or believe that they will.
There is merely a risk of such consequences, sufficiently great to lead
a reasonable man and his position to anticipate them, and to guard
against them. If an automobile driver runs down a man in
the street before him, with the desire to hit them, or with the belief
that he is certain to do so, it is an intentional battery; but if he
has no such desire or belief, but merely acts unreasonably and failing
to guard against risk which he should appreciate, it is
negligence. As a probability of injury to another apparent
from the facts within his knowledge, becomes greater, is conduct takes
on more of the attributes of intent, until it reaches that substantial
certainty of harm which juries, and sometimes courts, may find
inseparable from intent itself. Such intermediate mental
states, based upon a recognizable great probability of harm, may still
properly be classified as “negligence,” but are commonly called
“recklessness,” “wanton,” or even “willful.” They are dealt
with, in many respects, as if the harm were intended, so that they
become ineffective hybrid between intent negligence, occupying a sort
of penumbra between the two. They will be dealt with in a later section.
Negligence already has been defined is conduct which
falls below a standard established by the law for the protection of
others against unreasonable risk of harm. The idea of risk
necessarily involves a recognizable danger, based upon some knowledge
of the existing facts, and some reasonable belief that the harm may
follow. A risk is a danger which is apparent, or should be
apparent, to one in the position of the actor. The
culpability of the actor’s conduct must be judged in the light of the
possibilities apparent to him at the time, and not by looking backward
“with the wisdom born of the event.” The standard must be
one of conduct, rather than of consequences. It is not
enough that everyone can see now that the risk was great, if it was not
apparent when the conduct occurred. The court must put itself in the
actor’s place. At the same time, the standard impose must
be an external one, based upon what society demands of the individual,
rather than upon his own notions of what is proper. An
honest blunder, or mistaken belief that no damage will result, may
absolve him from moral blame, but the harm to others is still as great,
and the actors individual standards must give way to those of the
public. In other words, society may require them not to be
a fool.
In light of the
recognizable risk, the conduct, to be negligent, must be
unreasonable. Nearly all human acts, of course, carry some
recognizable but remote possibility of harm to another. No
man so much as rides a horse without some chance of a runaway, or
drives a car without the risk of a broken steering gear or a heart
attack. Those against which he actor is required to take
precautions are those which society, in general consider sufficiently
great to demand them. No man can be expected to guard against harm from
events which are not reasonably to be anticipated at all or are so
unlikely to occur that the risk, although recognizable, would commonly
be disregarded. An unprecedented frost or flood, and
automobile thrown unexpectedly against a pillar on the corner, a child
picking up a plank with a nail in it and dropping it on his foot, a
pedestrian slipping on a small bit of gravel in the highway, the
ricochet of a bullet and an almost impossible angle- all of these
things have happened, and will occur again; but they are not so likely
to do so on any particular occasion as to make it necessary to burden
the freedom of human action with precautions against them.
Such events are regarded as “unavoidable accidents,” for which there is
no liability.
On the other
hand, if the risk is an appreciable one, and the possible consequences
are serious, the question is not one of mathematical probability
alone. The odds may be 1001 that no train will arrive at the very
moment that an automobile is crossing a railway track, but the risk of
death is nevertheless sufficiently serious to require the driver to
look for the train. It may be highly improbable at
lightning will strike at any given place or time; but the possibility
is there, and it requires precautions for the protection of
inflammables. As a gravity of the possible harm increases,
the apparent likelihood of its occurrence need be correspondingly less.
Against this probability, and gravity, of the risk,
must be balanced in every case the utility of the type of conduct in
question. The problem is whether “the game is worth the
candle.” Many risk may reasonably be run, with full
approval of the community. Chief among the factors which must be
considered is the social value of the interest which the actor is
seeking to advance. A man may be justified in dashing into
the path of a train to save the life of a child, where it would be
arrant folly to save his hat. A railway will be permitted,
or even required, to blow a whistle to warn travelers at a crossing,
although it is likely to frighten horses on the highway; it may be
negligence to blow the same whistle without the same occasion for
warning. The public interest will justify the use of
dangerous machinery, so long as the benefits outweigh the risk, and a
railroad may reasonably be constructed near a highway, even at the
expense of some danger to those who use it.
The same balance between the threatened harm in the
utility of the actor’s conduct appears, of course, in the various
privileges, such as that of self-defense, which are recognized as
defenses to intentional torts. The difference lies in the
fact that, for historical reasons derived from the old action of
trespass, such intentional invasions of the interests of another are
regarded as prima facia wrongful, and the privileges a matter of excuse
or defense; while in negligence, which is to be traced primarily to the
action on the case, it is considered that no wrong at all has occurred
unless the defendant’s conduct has been unreasonable in the light of
the risk, and the burden is upon the plaintiff from the outset to
establish the fact.
Consideration must also be given to any alternative course open to the
actor. Whether it is reasonable to travel a dangerous road
may depend upon the disadvantages of another route; and while mere
inconvenience or cost may not themselves be sufficient to justify
proceeding in the face of great danger, they may justify taking other
risks which are not too extreme. A county will not be required,
at ruinous expense, to build a bridge which will be safe against any
accident that might be anticipated; but the converse is also true, and
working cheaply and easily post a warning, it may be required to do
so. A railroad need not do without a turntable because
there is some chance that children will play on it be hurt; but is
quite another matter to keep it locked.
The alternative dangerous to the actor himself and
others must be thrown into the scale, and balance struck in which all
of these elements are weighed.
It is fundamental that the standard of conduct which
is the basis of the law of negligence is determined by balancing the
risk, in the light of the social value of the interest threatened, and
the probability and extent of the harm, against the value of the
interest which the actor is seeking to protect, and the expedience of
the course pursued. For this reason, it is seldom possible
to reduce negligence 20 definite rules; it is “relative to the need and
the occasion,” and the conduct which would be proper under some
circumstances becomes negligence under others.
32. THE REASONABLE MAN
The whole theory of negligence presupposes some
uniform standard of behavior. Yet the infinite variety of
situations which may arise makes it impossible to fix definite rules in
advance for all conceivable human conduct. The utmost that
can be done is to devise something in the nature of the formula, the
application of which in each particular case must be left to the jury,
or to the court. The standard of conduct which the
community demands must be an external and objective one, rather than
the individual judgment, good or bad, of the particular actor; and it
must be, so far as possible, the same for all persons, since the law
can have no favorites. At the same time, it must make proper allowance
for the risk apparent to the actor, for his capacity to meet it, and
for the circumstances under which he must act.
The courts have dealt with this very difficult
problem by creating a fictitious person, who never has existed on land
or sea: the “reasonable man of ordinary prudence”.
Sometimes he is described as a reasonable man, or a prudent man, or a
man of average prudence, or a man of ordinary sense using ordinary care
and skill. It is evident that all such phrases are intended
to mean very much the same thing. The actor is required to
do what such an ideal individual would be supposed to do in his
place. A model of all proper qualities, with only those
human shortcomings and weaknesses which the community will tolerate on
the occasion, “this excellent but odious character stands like a
monument to our Courts of Justice, vainly appealing to his fellow
citizens to order their lives after his own example.”
The courts go to unusual pains to emphasize the
abstract and hypothetical character of this mythical
person. He is not to be identified with any ordinary
individual, who might occasionally do unreasonable things; he is
a prudent and careful man, who is always up to standard.
Nor is it proper to identify him even with any member of the very jury
who are to apply the standard; he is rather a personification of a
community ideal of reasonable behavior, determined by the jury’s social
judgment. Is sometimes difficult to escape the conviction
that the refinements which have been developed in instructing the jury,
in the effort to avoid any personal standard which one of them might be
tempted to apply, artificial and unreal, and quite beyond the
comprehension of the average man in the box. Their only
possible justification lies in a basis of experience justifying
considerable uneasiness about what any jury may conceivably do, which
has led to an excess of precaution in the effort to give them proper
guidance.
Physical Attributes
The conduct of the reasonable man will vary with the
situation with which he is confronted. The jury must
therefore be instructed to take the circumstances into account;
negligence is failure to do with the reasonable man would do “under the
same or similar circumstances.” Under the latitude of this
phrase, the courts have made allowance not only for the external facts,
but for many of the characteristics of the actor himself, and have
applied, in many respects, a more or less subjective standard. “It
would appear that there is no standardized man; that there is
only in part an objective test; that there is no such thing as
reasonable or unreasonable conduct except as viewed with reference to
certain qualities of the actor - his physical attributes, his
intellectual powers, probably, if superior, his knowledge and the
knowledge he would’ve acquired haddie exercise standard moral and at
least average mental qualities at the time of action or at some
connected time.”
As to his
physical characteristics, the reasonable man may be said to be
identical with the actor. The man who is blind or deaf, or
lame, or is otherwise physically disabled, is entitled to live in the
world and to have allowance made by others for his disability, and he
cannot be required to do the impossible by conforming to physical
standards which he cannot meet. Similar allowance has been
made for the weakness of age and sex. At the same time, the
conduct of the handicapped individual must be reasonable in light of
his knowledge of his infirmity, which is treated merely as one of the
circumstances under which he asked. A blind man may be
negligent in going to a place of known danger, just as one who knows
that he is subject to epileptic fits, or is about to fall asleep, may
be negligent driving the car. Is sometimes said that a
blind man must use a greater degree of care then one who can see;
but it is now generally agreed that as a fixed rule this is inaccurate,
and that the correct statement is merely that he must take the
precautions, be they more or less, which the ordinary reasonable man
would take if you were blind. In theory the standard
remains the same, but is sufficiently flexible to take his physical
defects into account.
Footnote 17. “Negligence is the
omission to do something which reasonable man, guided upon those
considerations which ordinarily regulate the conduct of human affairs,
would do, or doing something which a prudent and reasonable man would
not do.” Anderson, B., in Blyth v. Birmingham Waterworks Co.,
1856, 11 Ex. 781, 784, 156 Eng. Rep. 1047.
Automobile Guest
Statutes
Page 186
The automobile Guest statutes, which have been
mentioned in passing, have been adopted in rather more than half of the
states. They provide that the driver of an automobile is
liable to one who is writing as a gratuitous guest in his car only for
some form of aggravated misconduct. These statutes, which
have been held constitutional, vary considerably in their language from
state to state, according to the fancy of the legislature or
compromises in drawing the particular act. The required
form of aggravation is specified as “gross negligence,” “intentional,”
“willful,” “wanton,” or “reckless” misconduct, acting “in disregard of
the safety of others,” “intoxication,” or some combination of two or
more. There is so much individual variation in the
statutes, and in their interpretation, that it may safely be said that
there are as many different guest laws as there are acts.
Such statutes have been the result of persistent
effective lobbying on the part of liability insurance
companies. The chief argument advanced in support of them
has been that in guest cases the insurer, who is required to pay the
damages, is peculiarly exposed to collusion between the injured guest
and a host anxious to see compensation paid, so long as he does not
have to pay it - so that the truth does not come out in court, and
there is a resulting increase in insurance rates.
Essentially, however, the theory of the acts is that one who receives a
gratuitous favor in the form of a free ride has no right to demand that
his hose shall exercise ordinary care not to injure them.
The typical guest act case is that of the driver who offers his friend
a lift to the office or invites him out to dinner, negligently drives
him into a collision, and fractures his skull- after which driver and
his insurance company take refuge in the statute, step out of the
picture, and leave the guest to bear his own loss. If this
is good social policy, it at least appears under a novel front.
There is perhaps no other group of statutes which
have filled the courts with appeals on so many knotty little problems
involving petty and otherwise entirely inconsequential points of
law. There is first of all the question of who is a
“guest.” What is the effect of sharing expenses, or of the
guest buying a tank of gasoline? Of an indirect,
prospective, or merely remotely potential, benefit to the host in the
form of some business interest or hope in having the guest take the
ride? Of an employer’s order prohibiting the driver from
taking free riders; of the fact that the guest is not invited, but
allowed to stay after each rest passes; of the fact that the plaintiff
is a child too young to know that he is a guest? Of the
fact that the guest was out of the car for a moment when he was run
down; of his demand to be let out of the car; of his assent even to the
aggravated misconduct? Can the owner of the car be a guest
in it when someone else is driving? And finally, what is
the meaning, and application, of “gross,” “willful,” “wanton,”
“reckless,” or whatever other terms a statute may adopt?
No short text can hope deal with the infinite
variety of answers to these questions, under the different statutes,
and so many states. The reader can only be referred to the law of
the jurisdiction in which he may be interested.
35. RULES OF LAW
Page 188
The entire system of common-law jurisprudence has
been built upon the principle of stare decisis, that a decision of an
appellate court establishes a precedent, to be followed in that
jurisdiction when similar fact situation shall arise again.
The principal has value in so far as it makes it possible to predict in
advance the course which the administration of justice will take, and
secures against bad motives or errors in judgment on the part of
individual judges, or serves to prevent the sacrifice of ultimate
social interest to the immediate demands of a particular
case. But it is not, and never has been, and ironclad an
absolute principle, and such precedents may be departed from when the
court subsequently concludes that they are unreasonable, or out of line
with altered social conditions. Nor do they control when
the facts arise are essentially different; and many writers have
devoted thought to the sometimes highly artificial technique by which
the facts of earlier cases are “distinguished.”
A decision of an appellate court that under certain
circumstances a particular type of conduct is clearly negligent, or
that it clearly is not negligent, or that the issue is for the jury as
one in which reasonable men may differ, establishes a precedent for
other cases where the facts are identical, or substantially the
same. To that extent may define the standard of reasonable
conduct which a community requires. Unfortunately the inevitable
tendency to crystallize the law into mechanical rules has led the
courts in many cases to treat such precedents as fixing definite rules
of universal application. Almost invariably the rule has
broken down in the face of the obvious necessity of basing the standard
upon the particular circumstances, the apparent risk in the actors
opportunity to deal with it.
Especially noteworthy in this respect is the attempt
of Mr. Justice Holmes, in Baltimore and Ohio Railway versus Goodman, to
“lay down a standard once and for all,” which would require an
automobile driver approaching a railroad crossing with an obstructed
view to stop, look and listen, and if he cannot be sure otherwise that
no train is coming, to get out of the car. The basic idea behind
this is sound enough: it is by no means proper care to cross a railroad
track without taking reasonable precautions against a train, and
normally such precautions will require looking, hearing, and to stop,
or at least slow speed, where the view is obstructed. But the
attempt to specify conduct for all cases virtually made it certain that
there could never be a recovery for crossing accident. A
long series of cases in which gates were left open, or the driver
relied upon the absence of a flagman, or it was clear that the conduct
specified would’ve added nothing to the driver safety, made it quite
apparent that no such inflexible rule could be applied.
Finally, in the subsequent case of Pokora v. Wabash Railroad, where the
only effective stop must be made upon the railway tracks themselves, in
a position of obvious danger, the court discarded any such uniform
rule, rejecting the “get out of the car” requirement as “an uncommon
precaution common likely to be futile and sometimes even dangerous,”
and saying that the driver need not always stop.
“Illustration such as these,” said Mr. Justice Cardozo, “bear witness
to the need for caution in framing standards of behavior that amount to
rules of law. Extraordinary situations may not wisely or
fairly be subjected to tests or regulations that are fitting for the
common place or normal.”
A
similar fate is overtaking the rule which many courts have stated, that
it is always negligence to drive at such a speed that it is impossible
to stop within the range of vision. Again the principle is
sound enough; but universal application becomes quite impossible.
The rule is proved to be much too stringent when visibility is obscured
by fog or rain, when the driver suddenly blinded by the lights of an
approaching car, or when unanticipated defects or obstacles suddenly
appear on an apparently safe highway. The reaction from the rule has
been so marked that some courts have gone to the other extreme, of
saying that such speed is never more than evidence of negligence for
the jury. Similar difficulties have arisen as to the
ordinary traffic “rules of the road,” and the rule that a pedestrian
must look when crossing a street, that a driver must constantly watch
the road ahead, or that it is negligence to border leave a train while
it is in motion.
Such
rules may be useful to fix the standard for the usual normal case but
they are a hindrance to any just decision in the large number of
unusual situations presenting new factors which may affect the
standard. A standard which requires only conduct
proportionate to the circumstances and the risk seldom, if ever, can be
made a matter of absolute rule.
36. VIOLATION OF STATUTE
Page 190
The standard of conduct required of a reasonable man
may be prescribed by legislative enactment. When a statute
provides that under certain circumstances particular act shall or shall
not be done, it may be interpreted as fixing a standard for all members
of the community, from which it is negligence to deviate.
Within the limits of municipal authority, the same may be true of
ordinances. The fact that such legislation is usually penal
in character, and carries with it a criminal penalty, will not prevent
its use in imposing civil liability, except in the comparatively rare
case where the penalty is made payable to the person injured, and
clearly is intended to be in lieu of all other compensation.
Much ingenuity has been expended in the effort to
explain why criminal legislation should result in a rule for civil
liability. If there is a specific provision in the statute
to that effect there is a course no difficulty, since it is clear that
it is the intent of the legislature. The only questions
open or whether the legislation is constitutional, whether it is
applicable to the particular case, and whether it has in fact been
violated. But where the statute merely declares that
conduct is a crime, and makes no mention of any civil remedy,
justification becomes more difficult, since a courtesan obviously under
no compulsion to apply the statute. Many courts have,
however, purported to “find” in the statute is suppose it “implied,”
“constructive,” or “presumed” intent to provide for tort
liability. In the ordinary case this is pure fiction,
concocted for the purpose. The obvious conclusion can only
be that when the legislator said nothing about it, they either did not
have the civil suit in mind at all, or deliberately omitted to provide
for it. Again, it is said that the reasonable man would
obey the criminal law, and that one who does not is not acting as
reasonable man, and therefore must be negligent. While this
may serve to explain the decision that a breach of the statute is
evidence of negligence, it is not clear that it justifies a prevailing
rule under which the court must refuse to leave the issue to the jury,
nor does it account for the numerous violations which are held not to
give rise to any civil action at all, or for the cases in which, on the
basis of analogy or association, the liability has been rested upon
some other tort, such as trespass, deceit, nuisance, or even strict
liability.
Perhaps the
most satisfactory explanation is that the courts are seeking, by
something in the nature of judicial legislation, to further the
ultimate policy for the protection of individuals which they find
underlying the statute, and which they believe the legislature must
have had mine. The statutory standard of conduct is simply
adopted voluntarily, out of the deference and respect for the
legislature. This is borne out by a considerable number of cases
in which the terms of a criminal statute have been applied in a civil
action, notwithstanding the fact the statute was for some reason
totally ineffective as a basis for criminal conviction - as where it
had not been properly enacted, or did not exactly cover the situation,
or the defendant was incapable of crime, and could not be prosecuted;
and by one or two others in which there has been flat refusal to accept
a standard regarded as unreasonable.
The question thus becomes one of when the court will
look to a criminal statute for its negligence standard of the conduct
of a reasonable man.
Footnote 79. “Negligence and
willfulness are as un-mixable as oil and water. ‘Willful negligence’ is
as self-contradictory as ‘guilty innocence.’” Kelly v. Malott, 7 Cir.
1905, 135 F. 74; Neary v. Northern Pac. R. Co. 1910, 41 Mont.
480, 490, 110 P. 226; Michaels v. Boruta, Tex.Civ.App.1938, 122 S.W.2d
216
Chapter 7
PROXIMATE CAUSE
Sec. 41. CAUSATION IN FACT
p. 236 – 241
Causation is a fact. It is a matter of what
has in fact
occurred. A cause is a necessary antecedent: in a
very real and practical sense, the term embraces all things which have
so far contributed to the result that without them it would not have
occurred. It covers not only positive acts and active
physical forces, but also pre-existing passive conditions which have
played a material part in bringing about the event. In
particular, it covers the defendants omissions as well as his
acts. The failure to extinguish a fire may be quite as
important in causing the destruction of the building is setting it in
the first place. The failure to fence a railway track may
be a cause, and an important one, that a child is struck by
train. It is familiar law that if such omissions are
culpable they will result in liability.
On
the other hand, an act or omission is not regarded as a cause of an
event if the particular event would’ve occurred without it.
A failure to fence a hole in the ice plays no part in causing the death
of runaway horses which could not have been halted if the fence had not
been there. A failure to have a lifeboat ready is not a
cause of the death of a man who syncs without trace immediately upon
falling into the ocean. The failure to install proper fire
escape on a hotel is no cause the death of a man suffocated in his bed
by smoke. The omission of a traffic signal to an automobile
driver who could not have seen it if it had been given is not a cause
of the ensuing collision. The omission of crossing signals
by an approaching train is of no significance when an automobile driver
runs into the 68th car. The presence of a railroad
embankment may be no cause of the inundation of the plaintiffs land by
a cloudburst which would have flooded it in any case.
From such cases many courts have derived a rule,
commonly known as the
“but for” or “sine qua non“ rule, which may be stated as follows:
The defendant’s conduct is not a cause of the event, if the event would
have occurred without it. At most this must be a rule of
exclusion: if the event would not have occurred “but for” the
defendant’s negligence, it still does not follow that there is
liability, since considerations other than causation, which remain to
be discussed, may prevent it. It should be quite obvious
that, once events are set in motion, there is, in terms of causation
alone, no place to stop. The event without millions of
causes is simply inconceivable; and causation alone can provide no clue
of any kind to single out those which are to be held legally
responsible. It is for this reason that instructions to the
jury that they must find the defendant’s conduct to be “the sole
cause”, or “the dominant cause”, or “the proximate cause” of the injury
are rightly condemned as misleading error.
Restricted to the question of causation alone, and
regarded merely as a
rule of exclusion, the “but for” rule serves to explain the greater
number of cases; but there is one type of situation in which it
fails. If two causes concur to bring about an event, and
either one of them, operating alone, would’ve been sufficient cause he
identical result, some other test is needed. To motorcycle
simultaneously past the plaintiff’s horse, which is frightened and runs
away; either one alone would’ve caused the fright. A stabs
C with a knife, and B fractures C’s skull with the rock; either wound
would be fatal, and C dies from the effects of both. The
defendant sets a fire, which merges with the fire from some other
source; the combined fires burn the plaintiff’s property, but either
one would have done it alone. In such cases it is quite
clear that each cause has in fact played so important a part in
producing the result that responsibility should be imposed upon it; and
it is equally clear that neither can be absolved from that
responsibility upon the ground that the identical harm would’ve
occurred without it, or there would be no liability at all.
It was in a case of this type that the Minnesota
court applied a
broader rule, which has found general acceptance: the defendant’s
conduct is a cause of the event if it was a material element and a
substantial factor in bringing it about. Whether it was
such a substantial factor is for the jury to determine, unless the
issue is so clear that reasonable men could not differ. It
is been considered that “substantial factor” is a phrase sufficiently
intelligible to the layman to furnish an adequate guide and
instructions to the jury, and that it is neither possible nor desirable
to reduce it to any lower terms. As applied to the fact of
causation alone, no better test is been devised.
Such a formula can scarcely be called a test, is
clearly an
improvement over the “but for” rule. It
disposes of the cases mentioned above, and likewise of the difficulties
presented by two other types of situations which have proved
troublesome. One is that were similar, but not identical
result would’ve followed without defendants act; the other where one
defendant has made a clearly prove but quite insignificant contribution
to the result, as where he throws a lighted match into a forest
fire. But in the great majority of cases, it amounts to the
same thing. Except as indicated, no case has been found
where the defendants act could be called a substantial factor when the
event would’ve occurred without it; nor will cases very often arise
where it would not be such a factor when it was so indispensable a
cause that without it the result would not of followed.
If the defendant’s conduct was a substantial factor
in causing the
plaintiff’s injury, it follows that he will not be absolved from
liability merely because the other causes have contributed to the
result, since such causes, innumerable, are always present.
In particular, however, a defendant is not necessarily relieved of
liability because the negligence of another person is also a
contributing cause, and that person, too, is to be held
liable. Thus were two vehicles collided and injure a
bystander, or passenger and one of them, each driver may be liable for
the harm inflicted. The law of joint tortfeasors rests very
largely upon recognition of the fact that each of the two or more
causes may be charged with a single result.
It cannot be repeated too often that, while
causation is essential to
liability, it does not determine it. Other
considerations, which remain to be considered, may prevent liability
for results clearly cause.
Proof
On
the issue of the fact of causation, as on other issues essential to his
cause of action for negligence, the plaintiff, in general, has the
burden of proof. He must introduce evidence which affords a
reasonable basis for the conclusion that is more likely than not that
the conduct of the defendant was a substantial factor in bringing about
the result. A mere possibility of such causation is not
enough; and when the matter remains one of pure speculation or
conjecture, or the probabilities are at best evenly balanced, it
becomes the duty of the court to direct a verdict for the
defendant. Where the conclusion is not one within the
common knowledge of layman, expert testimony may provide a sufficient
basis for it, but in the absence of such testimony may not be drawn.
Chapter 9
NEGLIGENCE: PROOF
p. 205
37. FUNCTIONS OF COURT AND JURY
The existence of negligence is a particular case
often is said to b a mixed question of law and fact. By
this is meant, not only that both the court and the jury have an
important part to play in the determination of the issue, and that
separate functions are assigned to each, but further, that these
functions to some extent overlap, and that it is not easy to fix any
definite line of demarcation. It is said also that the
court must decide questions of law, and the jury questions of
fact. But this means little or nothing until some method of
classification is provided, by which "law" may be distinguished from
"fact"; and the division of functions between court and jury is a
matter rather of historical origins and present policy than of any such
definitions.
The issue of negligence presents at least five more or less distinct
questions, as to which the court and the jury have separate parts to
play in reaching a decision. These are as follows:
1. The sufficiency of the evidence to
permit a finding of the facts. Before any duty, or any
standard of conduct may be set, there must first be proof of facts
which give rise to it; and once the standard is fixed, there must
be proof that the actor has departed from it. If it be
assumed that the driver of an automobile approaching a visible
intersection will be required to moderate his speed, there is still the
question whether the intersection was visible, and whether he did in
fact slow down. These are purely questions of fact, and
within the recognized province of the jury as the triers of
fact. But over such questions of fact the court always have
reserved a preliminary power of decision, as to whether the issue shall
be submitted to the jury at all. If the evidence is such
that no reasonably intelligent man would accept it as sufficient to
establish the existence of a fact essential to negligence, it becomes
the duty of the court to remove the issue from the jury, and to nonsuit
the plaintiff, or direct a verdict for the defendant, or even to set
aside a verdict once rendered. Less frequently, the
evidence may be so overwhelming that no reasonable man could fail to
accept the fact as proved; and the court must then direct
the jury accordingly.(5) This, of course, merely a part of
the general law of evidence, and in this respect negligence cases do
not differ from any other cases where essential facts must be proved.
3. The existence of a duty.
In other words, whether, upon the facts in evidence, such a relation
exists between the parties that the community will impose a legal
obligation upon one for the benefit of the other - or more simply,
whether the interest of the plaintiff which has suffered invasion was
entitled to legal protection at the hands of the defendant.
This is entirely a question of law, to be determined by reference to
the body of statutes, rules, principles and precedents which make up
law; and it must be determined only by the court. It
is no part of the province of a jury to decide whether a manufacturer
of goods is the ultimate consumer, or whether the Long Island Railroad
is required to protect Mrs. Palsgraf from fireworks
explosions. A decision by the court that upon any version
of the facts, there is no duty, must necessarily result in judgement
for the defendant. A decision that, if certain facts are
found to be true, a duty exists, leaves open the other questions now
under consideration.
Fn.
5. This is true, for example, where the "incontrovertible
physical facts" contradict the actor's testimony as to his use of care
- as where he is paced in the familiar dilemma that he either must not
ave looked, must have failed to observe what was plainly visible, or
must have disregarded what he saw.
Heindel v. Transcontinental Ins. & Co.,
La.App.1955, 82 So.2d 491; Miller v. North Carolina R. Co., 1942, 220
N.C. 562, 18 S.E.2d 232; Krause v. Baltimore & O. R. Co., 1944, 183
Md. 664, 39 A2d 795; Danks v. Pittsburgh R. Co., 1937, 328 Pa. 356, 195
A. 16; Chandler v. Buchannan, 1927, 173 Minn. 31, 216 N.W.
254. See Note, 1932, 37 Dick.L.Rev. 58.
Chapter
12
IMPUTED NEGLIGENCE
p. 482 - 483
But some courts clearly have gone
further, and have held that the right of control, sufficient to impose
responsibility, is established by the mere presence of the owner in the
car. Most jurisdictions have rejected such an arbitrary
rule, and have held that the owner may surrender his right to give
directions, and become a guest in his own car. It is
generally agreed that the plaintiff may be aided by a presumption that
the driver is an agent or servant, but the owner may prove the contrary.
If the owner is not present in
the car, but has entrusted it to a driver who is not his servant, there
is merely a bailment, and usually no basis can be found for even any
fiction of a “right of control.” It is here that the
owner’s liability to the injured plaintiff breaks down at common
law. Only the courts of Florida have gone to the length of
saying that an automobile is a “dangerous instrumentality,” for which
the owner remains responsible when it is negligently driven by
another. Other courts have refused to accept this simple
but sweeping conclusion, and have fallen back instead upon a mere
presumption that the driver is the servant of the owner, which may be
rebutted, or have struggled hard to find some foundation for vicarious
liability in the circumstances of the particular case.
Family Purpose
Doctrine
One of the devices most commonly
resorted to is the “family car,” or “family purpose” doctrine, which
has been accepted by about half of the American courts.
Under this doctrine, the owner of an automobile who permits members of
his household to drive it for their own pleasure or convenience is
regarded as making such a family purpose his “business,” so that the
driver is treated as his servant. Sometimes it is said that
the owner would be liable for the negligence of a chauffeur whom he
hires to drive his family, and therefore should be liable when he
entrusts the same task to a member of his family instead.
This is obviously an element of unblushing fiction in this manufactured
agency; and it has quite often been recognized, without apology,
that the doctrine is an instrument of policy, a transparent device
intended to place the liability upon the party most easily held
responsible.
Chapter
13
STRICT LIABILITY
p. 492
75. BASIS OF LIABILITY
As we have seen, the early law of torts was
not concerned primarily with the moral responsibility, or “fault” of
the wrongdoer. It occupied itself chiefly with keeping the
peace between individual, by providing a remedy which would be accepted
in lieu of private vengeance. While it is probable that
even from the beginning the idea of moral guilt never was entirely
absent from the minds of the judges, it was not the most important
consideration. Originally the man who hurt another by pure
accident, or in self-defense, was required to make good the damage
inflicted. “In all civil acts,” it was said, “the law doth
not so much regard the intent of the actor, as the loss and damage to
the party suffering.”1 There was, in other words, a rule,
undoubtedly supported by the general feeling in the community, that “he
who breaks must pay.”
Until about the close of the nineteenth century, the history of the law
of torts was that of a slow, and somewhat unsteady, progress toward the
recognition of “fault” or moral responsibility with conduct which would
not be expected of a good citizen. This tendency was
so marked that efforts were made by noted writers to construct a
consistent theory of tort law upon the basic principle that there
should be no liability without fault.
But “fault” in this sense never has become quite
synonymous with moral blame. Not only is a great deal of
morally reprehensible conduct vested with complete legal immunity - as
where the expert swimmer who sees another drowning before his eyes is
permitted to stand on the dock and watch him drown - but at the same
time the law finds “fault” in much that is morally
innocent. “Fault” is a failure to live up to an ideal of
conduct to which no one conforms always and which may be beyond the
capacity of the individual. It may consist of sheer
ignorance, lack of intelligence or an honest mistake. It
may consist even in acts which are the normal and usual thing in the
community. Even the infant and the lunatic who can not help
what they do are held liable for their torts.
So much can be collected in the way of cause
imposing liability without any vestige of moral blame that a number of
writers have maintained that negligence is rapidly losing, if it has
not entirely lose, its character as a branch of “fault” liability, so
that those who are entirely innocent are now required to pay for the
damage they do, and that negligence should therefore largely be
jettisoned. This perhaps begs the question, by assigning to
“fault” a criminal law connotation of moral blame which it seldom has
been given in the law of torts. There is a broader sense in
which “fault” means nothing more than departure from a standard of
conduct required of a man by society for the protection of his
neighbors; and if the departure is an innocent one, and the
defendant cannot help it, it is none the less a departure, and a social
wrong. The distinction still remains between the man who
has deviated from the standard, and the man who has not.
The defendant nay not be to blame for being out of line with what
society requires of him, but he is none the less out of line.
In this broader sense there is “fault” in much
innocent conduct. Tort liability never has been
inconsistent with the ignorance which is bliss, or the good intentions
with which hell is said to be paved. A trespasser is not
excused by the honest reasonable belief that the land is his own;
a bona fide purchaser of stolen goods is held liable for
conversion; the publisher of a libel commits a tort, although he
has no means of knowing the defamatory nature of his
words. There are many situations in which a careful person
is held liable for an entirely reasonable mistake.
Socially, and legally, these defendants are at fault; whether
they are individually so, in spite of the fact that they are blameless,
appears to be entirely a matter of definition, rather than substance,
and the argument leads only to a pointless dispute over the meaning of
a word.
1. Lambert v. Bessey, 1681, T.Ray. 421, 83 Eng.Rep. 220. As late
as 1783, “Erskin said in his argument in the celebrated case of The
Dean of St. Asaph [21 St.Tr.1022](and he said it by way of a familiar
illustration of the difference between civil and criminal liability)
that ‘if a man rising in his sleep walks into a china shop and breaks
everything about him, his being asleep is a complete answer to an
indictment for trespass, but he must answer in an action for everything
he has broken.’” Pollock, Law of Torts, 13.... Ed.1929, 146
Chapter
18
MISREPRESENTATION
p. 683
105. REMEDIES FOR
MISREPRESENTATION
Misrepresentation runs all through the law of torts,
as a method of accomplishing various types of tortious conduct which,
for reasons of historical development or as a matter of convenience,
usually are grouped under categories of their own.
Thus a battery may be committed by feeding the
plaintiff poisoned chocolates, or by inducing his consent to a physical
contact by misrepresenting its character; false imprisonment may result
from a pretense of authority to make an arrest, a trespass to land from
fraudulent statements inducing another to enter, or a conversion from
obtaining possession of goods by false representations; and a malicious
lie may give rise to a cause of action for the intentional infliction
of mental suffering. A great many of the common and
familiar forms of negligent conduct, resulting in invasions of tangible
interests of person or property, are in their essence nothing more than
misrepresentation, from a misleading signal by a driver of an
automobile about to make a turn, or an assurance that a danger does no
exist, to false statements concerning a chattel sold, or non-disclosure
of a latent defect by one who is under a duty to give
warning. In addition, misrepresentation may play an
important part in the invasion of intangible interests, in such torts
as defamation, malicious prosecution, or interference with contractual
relations. In all such cases the particular form which the
defendant's conduct has taken has become relatively unimportant, and
misrepresentation has been merged to such an extent with other kinds of
misconduct that neither the courts nor the legal writers have found any
occasion to regard it as a separate basis of liability.
So far misrepresentation has been treated as giving
rise in and of itself to a distinct cause of action in tort, it has
been identified with the common law action of deceit. The
reasons for the separate development of this action and for its
peculiar limitations, are in part historical, and in part connected
with the fat that in the great majority of the cases which have come
before the courts the misrepresentations have been made in the course
of a bargaining transaction between the parties.
Consequently the action has been colored to a considerable extent by
the ethics of bargaining between distrustful adversaries.
Its separate recognition has been confined in practice very largely to
the invasion of interests of a financial or commercial character, in
the course of business dealings. There is no essential reason to
prevent a deceit action from being maintained, for intentional
misstatements at a least, where other types of interests are
invaded; and there are a few cases in which it has been
held to lie for personal injuries, for tricking the plaintiff into an
invalid marriage or marriage with one who is physically unfit, or for
inducing the plaintiff to leave a husband, or to incur criminal
penalties. In general, however, other theories of action
have been sufficient to deal with non-pecuniary damage, and the
somewhat narrower theory of deceit is one in which the plaintiff has
parted with money, or property of value, in reliance upon the
defendant's representations.
The law of misrepresentation is thus considerably
broader than the action for deceit. Liability in damages
for misrepresentation, in one form or another, falls into the three
familiar divisions with which we have dealt throughout this text - it
may be based upon intent to deceive, upon negligence, or upon a policy
which requires the defendant to be strictly responsible for his
statements without either. For the most part, the courts
have limited deceit to those cases where there is an intent to mislead,
and have left negligence and strict liability to be dealt with in some
other type of action. There has been a good deal of
overlapping of theories, and no little confusion, which has been
increased by the indiscriminate use of the word "fraud," a term so
vague that it requires definition in nearly every case.
Further difficulty has been added by a failure to distinguish the
requisites of the action in tort at law from those of equitable
remedies, and to distinguish the different forms of misrepresentation
from one another, and misrepresentation itself from mere
mistake. Any attempt to bring order out of the resulting
chaos must be at best a tentative one, with the qualification that many
courts do not agree.
Deceit
The action of deceit is of very ancient
origin. There was an old writ of deceit known as early as
1201, which lay only against a person who had misused legal procedure
for the purpose of swindling someone. At a later period
this writ was superseded by an action on the case in the nature of
deceit, which became the general common law remedy for fraudulent or
even non-fraudulent misrepresentation resulting in actual
damage. In particular, it was extended to afford a remedy
for many wrongs which we should now regards as breaches of contract,
such as false warranties in the sale of goods. Its use was
limited almost entirely to cases of direct transactions between the
parties,, and it came to be regarded as inseparable from some
contractual relation. It was not until 1789, in Pasley v.
Freeman, which is the parent of the modern law of deceit, that the
action was held to lie where the plaintiff had had no dealings with the
defendant, but had been induced by his misrepresentation to deal with a
third person. After that date deceit was recognized as
purely a tort action, and not necessarily upon contract. At
about the same time, the remedy for a breach of warranty was taken over
into an action of assumpsit, and it was thus established that it had a
contract character. Thereafter the two lines of recovery
slowly diverged, although some vestiges of confusion between the two
still remain in many courts, particularly as to the measure of
damages. The distinction was made clear in English courts
by decisions holding that the tort action of deceit requires something
in the way of knowledge of the falsity of the statement and an
intention mislead, while the contact action on a warranty does not.
The elements of the tort cause of action and deceit
which it last emerged from this process of development frequently have
been stated as follows:
1. A false
representation made by the defendant. In the ordinary case, this
representation must be one of fact.
2.
Knowledge or belief on the part of the defendant that the
representation is false - or, what is regarded as equivalent, that he
has not a sufficient basis of information to make it. This
element often is given the technical name of “scienter.”
3. An intention to induce the plaintiff to act or
refrain from action in reliance upon the misrepresentation.
4.
Justifiable reliance upon the representation on the part of the
plaintiff, and taking action or refraining from it.
5. Damage to the plaintiff, resulting from such
reliance.
As will be seen, some of these elements have
undergone modification or qualification in some
jurisdictions. In addition, it must be repeated that such
an action of deceit is only one of several possible remedies for
various forms of misrepresentation, even where there is only pecuniary
loss. Before proceeding to consider the elements of the
cause of action and deceit, it is desirable to distinguish other
theories upon which relief may be granted, the proximity of which has
been a fertile source of the general confusion and uncertainty
surrounding the deceit action itself.
Distinguished from Warranty and
Negligence
The divorce of warranty from deceit was completed by
about the beginning of the 19th century. By that time
warranty had become identified, at least in lawyers usage, with the
existence of a contract between the parties. Although the
original tort form of the action still survives as a possible
procedural alternative, and the tort theory may have important
consequences, there are only a limited number of cases, and those
entirely concerned with the liability of a seller of goods to the
ultimate consumer, in which warranty has been found without a
contract. Deceit, on the other hand, is essentially a tort
action, and does not require the existence of any contract, although of
course the tort itself may often coincide with one.
Furthermore, because of its contract character, warranty has become a
matter of strict liability, without any wrongful intent or negligence
on the part of the defendant, while deceit, as it developed in the law
of England, is to be classified as an intentional tort, requiring
knowledge or belief of falsity or conscious ignorance of the truth, and
hence something of an intent to mislead. In the American
courts, the distinction is not always clearly drawn, and it is been
obscured or abandoned in many jurisdictions by decisions which in
effect taken over the strict liability of warranty and adopted it and
deceit form of action.
The
same intentional element distinguished to see, as it is defined by the
English courts and by many American jurisdictions, from
negligence. In finding the necessary “knowledge” as to the
falsity of the representation, these courts of stop short of the
situation where the defendant honestly believes that he knows and that
his statement is true, but is negligent in not obtaining accurate
information. There is nothing, however, to prevent an ordinary
negligence action for the use of language in such a case; and while
such an action is most often brought where damage which results is a
personal injury, it has been extended, with a somewhat restricted
scope, to cases involving financial or commercial loss.
In some jurisdictions, then, the distinction as to
the actions for deceit, negligence and warranty coincides in general
with that as to intent, negligence and strict liability. In
many courts, however, these lines have been blurred or obliterated by
an extension of the deceit action to cover all three types of
liability. The dispute over the proper form of action
frequently as obscure the real question of whether the defendant should
be held liable in the particular case. With the declining
importance of the foreman theory of the action under modern code
pleading, it is the latter which is the really important problem, with
which we must chiefly be concerned; and the discussion which is to
follow looks to the nature of the defendant’s conduct rather than the
form of his recovery.
Equitable Relief
To the difficulties arising from the existence of
these three strictly legal remedies, there must be added the further
confusion resulting from the possibility of equitable relief.
Misrepresentation was recognized very early as a basis for the
jurisdiction of courts of equity, at a time when the existing forms of
actions at law were in adequate to deal with the injustices which
resulted.
Page 687
CALIFORNIA JURY INSTRUCTIONS
CIVIL
Book of Approved Jury Instructions
[BAJI]
8th EDITION
BAJI 5.30
BASIC SPEED LAW
p. 144
The speed at which a vehicle is driven upon a highway [not in excess of
_______________ miles per hour], considered as an isolated fact and
simply in terms of so many miles an hour, is not proof either of
negligence or of the exercise of ordinary care.
Whether driving at that rate of speed is negligent, is a question of
fact, and answer to which depends on all the surrounding circumstances.
The basic speed law of this state [, as provided by
Section 22350 of our Vehicle Code,] is as follows:
“No person shall drive a vehicle upon a highway at a speed greater than
is reasonable or prudent having due regard for weather, visibility, the
traffic on, and the surface width of, the highway, and in no event at a
speed which endangers the safety of persons or property.”
A violation of this basic rule is
negligence.
SPEEDING IS NOT A CRIME! SPEEDING IS CIVIL MISBEHAVIOR! CRIMINAL PROCEDURE CAN NOT APPLY!
Michigan Law Review
Vol. 50, No. 7, (May, 1952)
pp. 1122 - 1124
TORTS - FALSE IMPRISONMENT -
PUBLIC NUISANCE - LIABILITY FOR DOUBLE PARKING
David F. Ulmer, S. Ed.
The
action of false imprisonment is based on the individual's freedom of
movement,4 requiring an unlawful and involuntary restraint on that
freedom imposed by force or a reasonable apprehension of the use of
force.5 Although neither malice nor lack of probable cause in
imposing the restraint are elements of the tort,6 there must be an
actual intent to confine.7 Moreover,
4 PROSSER, TORTS 67 (1941); 1 TORTS RESTATEMENT §35 (1934);
Great Atlantic & Pacific Tea Co. v. Smith, 281 Ky. 583, 136 S.W.
(2d) 759 (1939).
5 Sinclair Refining Co. v. Meek, 62 Ga. App. 850, 10 S.E.
(2d) 76 (1940); Powell v. Champion Fiber Co., 150 N.C. 12, 63 S.E. 159
(1908); Whitman v. Atchison, T. & S.F. Ry. Co., 85 Kan. 150, 116 P.
234 (1911). On the question of public humiliation as sufficient
restraint, see: Fenn v. Kroger Grocery & Baking Co., (Mo. 1919) 209
S.W. 885;
Jacques v. Childs Dining Hall Co., 244
Mass. 438, 138 N.E. 843 (1923), and the later Massachusetts case
greatly weakening the Jacques decision, Sweeney v. F. W. Woolworth Co.,
247 Mass. 277, 142 N.E. 50 (1924).
6 Meints v. Huntington, (8th Cir. 1921) 276 F. 245; 137
A.L.R. 495 (1942); Johnson v. Norfolk & W. Ry. Co., 82 W.Va. 692,
97 S.E. 189 (1918). But malice and probable cause are admissible on the
question of punitive damages. Lindquist v. Friedman's, Inc., 366 Ill.
232, 8 N.E. (2d) 625 (1937); Gamier v. Squires, 62 Kan. 321, 62 P. 1005
(1900).
7 1 TORTS RESTATEMENT
§35(1)(a) (1934); Wood v. Cummings, 197 Mass. 80, 83 N.E. 318 (1908).
In the principal case we can predicate an intent to restrain on the
proposition that the defendant intended the natural consequences of his
act.
COMMENTARIES
ON
THE LAW OF PERSONS
AND
PERSONAL PROPERTY.
BEING AN INTRODUCTION TO THE
STUDY OF CONTRACTS.
BY
THEODORE W. DWIGHT,
LATE PROFESSOR OF LAW AT COLUMBIA COLLEGE, NEW YORK.
EDITED BY
EDWARD F. DWIGHT,
OF THE NEW YORK BAR.
BOSTON
LITTLE, BROWN, AND COMPANY.
1894.
CHAPTER III.
THE RIGHTS OF PERSONS.
The rights of persons are commonly divided into absolute and
relative. Absolute rights are such as appertain to a person
considered independently of others. They are, in the common
law, the right of personal security, the right of personal liberty, and
the right of private property. A violation of either of
these rights constitutes a legal wrong. The word " wrong,"
as here used, does not involve moral obliquity, but simply means an
unlawful interference with a legal right.
"Duty" is a correlative word to "right." If A. has a legal
right, B. is under a legal duty not to interfere with that right.
"There is no right without a duty; no duty without a right."
Magna Charta, or the Great Charter, was wrested from King John by his
barons, at Runnymede, June 15, 1215. It is only necessary at present to
refer to one of its important provisions, which is as follows
: "No freeman shall be taken, or imprisoned, or disseized,
or outlawed, or exiled, or anywise destroyed ; nor will we go upon him
nor send upon him but by the lawful judgment of his peers or by the law
of the land. To none will we sell, to none will we deny or
delay, right or justice."
An indictment is a
written accusation presented under oath to the proper
court. It is the result of an inquiry into the question
whether there is a sufficient probability that the
accused has
committed a crime, to justify a trial. It is a legal device
designed to prevent, as far as possible, the trial of frivolous and
unfounded charges of crime. The proceeding before the grand jury
is ex parte (evidence for the state only being heard). The
indictment having been found, the trial of the charge belongs to the
so-called petty jury, consisting of twelve men, and is presided over by
a judge. The conclusion or verdict of the jury must be
unanimous. This provision of Magna Charta does not
interfere with the trial of prisoners charged with minor offences,
termed misdemeanors, on the formal suggestion of a prosecuting officer,
such as the Attorney-General, without an indictment. This
method of proceeding is termed an information.
In civil cases, trial by jury was secured by the Great Charter in the
common-law courts, but its provisions did not extend to the courts of
equity, nor to the ecclesiastical courts or courts of admiralty where
trials are had before a judge alone.
I.
— (1) No bill of attainder shall be passed, (a) The
prohibition as to such legislation extends to the States as
well. The meaning of the word " bill " in this clause is "
law." The vicious character of such legislation consists in
the fact, that it enacts guilt by statute, instead of establishing it
by judicial proceedings and a recognized method of trial.
When the punishment is less than death, the statute
is called a bill of pains and penalties.
The indictment is peculiar to criminal prosecutions. If the
grand jury " find the indictment," it contains the charge which the
accused is required to answer in accordance with legal requirements and
forms. After answering (pleading) that he is not guilty, he
is put upon his trial before an ordinary jury consisting of twelve
men. This clause denies to the court at the trial the power
to strike words out of the indictment as superfluous, without
submitting the case anew to the grand jury.
This system is derived by inference from the provision of Magna Charta,
already cited. If the crime is not " infamous," in the
sense already explained, the prosecuting officer may file a
statement
of the offence charged without the aid of a grand jury, in which he
lays before the court the facts relevant to the alleged
offence. This statement, drawn up in legal form, is termed
an "information."
c. He may have
the assistance of counsel for his defence. [sic] This right
was now for the first time secured by any national government, though
it appears at an earlier day in some of the State
constitutions. Counsel were not at that time allowed in
criminal cases in England, except in charges of high treason, and in
trials for the inferior grade of crimes, termed
misdemeanors. In charges of felonies, punishable with
death, counsel were not allowed. This was so until Sidney
Smith, with his brilliant sarcasm and invective and telling argument,
shamed Parliament into the enactment of a law allowing counsel in the
case of trials for felony. The statutes allowing counsel
are referred to in the note. It is greatly to the credit of
the framers of the New York constitution of 1777, that they were the
first among English speaking people to make the right of one accused of
a felonious crime secure by constitutional provision, in opposition to
the current of contemporary professional opinion in
England. The words are very sweeping: "In every
indictment for crimes or misdemeanors the party indicted shall be
allowed counsel, as in civil actions." A refusal by a court
to grant delay to enable counsel to make preparation may be equivalent
to a denial of the right to have counsel.
In
general, " due process of law " implies and includes a plaintiff
(actor), a defendant (reus), a judge (judex), regular allegations,
opportunity to answer, and a trial according to a settled course of
judicial proceedings.
Criminal trials by an
impartial jury of twelve men have been made in their substance
perpetually inviolable by State action.
An
assault is a threat to do bodily harm; a battery is the actual
carrying of the threat into effect. The distinctions upon
this subject are highly technical, and must be sought in the works upon
torts and the decided cases. The definition of an assault
and battery in a civil sense is not identical with that which prevails
in criminal law. The essence of a crime being intention,
where the intent is wanting no crime exists. But the object
of the civil action is to afford compensation in damages to an injured
party. It would embrace the case, for example, of an injury
committed by a lunatic. In such a case, however, only
actual damages could be recovered.
Duress. —
This subject here presents itself as related to the law of
contracts. There may be duress both by an attack upon
personal security and personal liberty, and, in a modified sense, upon
private property. The great feature of duress is that it
takes away or impairs one of the essential ingredients of a contract,
viz., assent. The discussion of this topic more
appropriately belongs to treatises on the law of contracts.
Injuries to the Health or Personal Comfort. — These are termed
"nuisances." The word cannot be more precisely
defined. It is a generally accepted principle that an
alleged nuisance must materially interfere with the ordinary physical
comfort of human existence, not merely according to elegant or dainty
modes of living, but according to plain, sober, and simple notions
among the people. A nuisance may be either public or
private. A public nuisance affects the community at large;
a private nuisance affects an individual. A public nuisance
may affect a single person or group of persons, and so become private
as to them. An action for damages, or other private remedy,
does not lie for a public nuisance ; while these remedies may be
resorted to in case of a private nuisance. An injunction is
also a suitable remedy; and there may be a proceeding to have the
nuisance removed, or, in technical language, "abated." The remedy for a
public nuisance is a criminal proceeding, by indictment or information,
and in a proper case, a proceeding in a court of equity by the
attorney-general.
Injuries to the Reputation.
— These are of two general classes: libel, and slander.
Libel is defamatory matter addressed to the eye; slander, to the
ear. Of the two, libel is deemed to be the more
aggravated. It is both a civil wrong and a criminal
offence. It is classed among crimes on account of its
supposed tendency to cause a breach of the peace. The only
proceeding in the case of slander is an action for damages. Defamation,
whether libellous
or slanderous, is actionable on the ground that
the party whose character is assailed has sustained an injury to his
reputation, for which he should receive reparation, and the only
available way of compensating him is for the court to award him a sum
of money as damages.
Personal Liberty.
The right to personal liberty is a great and primordial right protected
not only by the law, but by constitutional provisions, beyond the
clauses of Magna Charta already referred to. One of these
is the provision that excessive bail shall not be
required.' Another is the right of the people to be secure
in their persons, houses, etc., against unreasonable searches and
seizures, and that no warrant shall issue but upon probable cause,
supported by oath or affirmation, and particularly describing the
persons or things to be seized. This Amendment was aimed at
the abuse in England called " general warrant," whereby a person might
be arrested without cause and without being named when the warrant was
issued by a magistrate. The provision, preventing the
suspension of the writ of habeas corpus except in cases of rebellion or
invasion, should also be referred to. Similar provisions
are found in State constitutions.
Where
personal liberty is violated, the law provides both a compensative and
preventive remedy. Compensation is awarded as the result of
an action for damages, called an action for false imprisonment.
THE LAW
OF PERSONAL PROPERTY.
Section II. Taxation. — In American law, there is a general power of
taxation vested in each State in analogy to a like power in English
law, as well as a specific power lodged by the terms of the United
States Constitution in the general government. The one
power is implied; the other is express. In general, there
is no restriction found in the State constitutions upon the power to
tax. It can properly be exercised only for some public
purpose.
It would be in the highest degree
unjust to tax the community for the benefit of a particular
individual. If, however, the purpose be public, the power,
in the absence of special restriction, is unlimited, since the
occasions that may require the exercise of the taxing power cannot be
foreseen.
Section III. Eminent
Domain.
The obligation to provide compensation is secured by clauses both in
the United States and State Constitutions. The language
used is, “nor shall private property be taken for public use without
just compensation." This clause, as found in the United
States Constitution, is only intended as a restraint upon the action of
Congress, and not upon that of the States. It is on this
account that a like clause is found in various State Constitutions, in
order to bind State legislatures.
It is a
fundamental prerequisite to a claim for compensation under our law,
that some property should be taken. The language of the
constitutional provision is, " nor shall private property be taken for
public use without just compensation."
Section V. Regulation or Destruction of private Property under
the so-called " Police Power” - By the police power is meant that
authority in the State which regulates private affairs, including the
control and management of property, so as to make them consist with the
public welfare. Sometimes it is exercised by the State
itself, and again by municipalities, or by public officers, such as
commissioners of highways. When properly exercised, private
rights must yield to it.
I. The relation of the
exercise of this power to constitutional provisions.
(2) In the practical exercise of the police power, such methods of
proceeding must be resorted to as are usual in judicial
inquiries. Property is not to be taken arbitrarily, or without
due notice to the owners and a reasonable opportunity to be
heard. Under this head, it has been decided that in a seizure of
property under a police regulation, the law must provide for legal
notice to the owner of the nature and cause of title accusation, as
well as of the trial of the question whether there has been a violation
of law.
(16) " Police power " is largely
exercised in the various States through the medium of licenses to
follow a trade, pursuit, or avocation, such as a license to keep a
pool-table; " to lawyers to practise; to keepers of private
markets; to peddlers of sewing machines; to brokers in real estate; and
to hotel-keepers. Similar principles are extended to market
regulations; also to auctioneers; and to the regulation of
packing-houses engaged in the packing of provisions.
As we have seen, one mode of exercising the police power is through the
medium of a license. It is highly important to distinguish
between such a license and one required for revenue
purposes. The latter is a mere revenue measure, and has in
it no element of police regulation. It is but an exercise of the power
to tax in a particular manner. But a license considered as
a police measure cannot properly be treated as a mode of
taxation. Only a reasonable amount should be exacted for
the purpose of properly carrying out the provisions of the license law.
This distinction is of great consequence in determining the power of a
city by ordinance to regulate trades and occupations by means of
licenses. It may be that when the object is to regulate
exhibitions and places of amusement, a greater sum may properly be
exacted under the police power than in the case of ordinary trades and
occupations.
A license, thus regarded, is not
a contract. It may be revoked at pleasure. Accordingly, if
one under a license purchases property to sell again, for example,
pistols, he can be lawfully prohibited by a police regulation from
selling after his license has expired, particularly if sufficient time
was accorded to him to sell before the license expired. The
true theory of such a license is that it is but a permission to do an
act which without the permission could not be done.
III.
Instances of the unwarranted exercise of the police power. — A
State cannot, under a pretended exercise of the police power, impose a
restriction upon the individual citizen which does not in fact connect
itself with police regulation. Every citizen has a general
right to pursue a trade or business. If this be perfectly
lawful and in no way injurious to the health or welfare of others, it
would appear that it should not be prohibited, though it may be liable
to just taxation. The act of a State legislature violating
this doctrine may be ultra vires and void.
The "police power," though indispensable in a civilized country, is a
dangerous one, being capable of great abuse, and no invasion of the
liberty or property of a citizen should be allowed, unless public ends
require it or would be apparently promoted by it.
PART II
DISTINCTIONS PECULIAR TO PERSONAL
PROPERTY
CHAPTER I.
ATTRIBUTES OF OWNERSHIP,
INCLUDING THE POWER TO USE, SELL, EXCHANGE, ETC.
Various terms are used to indicate personal property. Among
these may be mentioned goods, chattels, wares, merchandise, and things
(either in possession or "in action"). These words, for the
most part, may be used indiscriminately. In the matter of
the construction of written instruments in which they are found, — such
as wills or statutes, — differences in their meaning may become
important. The word " chattel " has a very broad and
comprehensive meaning, including movable property in every variety of
form. The phrase " thing in action " is used of rights from
the point of view of their being enforceable in a court of justice,
including both contracts and causes of action springing from a tort or
wrong.
Section I. The Power to sell or
exchange. — It is a well-settled rule that the right of property in
chattels includes the free and unfettered right on the part of the
owner to make use of them and dispose of them as he may see fit, in the
way of enjoyment or profit, unless his act be inconsistent with the
public welfare. This clear right is secured by
constitutional provisions. These have already been noticed while
discussing the police power.
Without freedom of sale or exchange, ownership is
not complete.
Section II. The Right to abandon. — Ownership of personal property
appears also to include not only the power to give it away to another,
but also the right to abandon or destroy it, having due regard to the
rights of others. The right to abandon is not, however,
very well settled in the decisions.
CHAPTER III.
VARIOUS DISTINCTIONS OF OWNERSHIP.
Ownership may be either absolute or qualified, absolute or conditional,
complete or partial, legal or equitable, separate or joint.
These distinctions will be considered in separate sections.
Section I. Absolute and qualified Ownership. — The nature of the
property itself may be such as not to be susceptible of indefeasible
ownership. Reference is here made to the right of property
in animals. These, for the treatment of this subject, must
be classified into the ordinary domestic animals, and those by nature
wild. Wild animals, again, are divisible into those which
are partially tame and those which are wholly wild. As to
domestic animals, there is no question. One may have an
indefeasible property in them, which is as complete as if he owned an
inanimate chattel. The young of such animals in general
belong to the owner of the dam, except in the case of young swans
(cygnets), which belong equally to the owner of the sire and dam,
assuming that these are owned by different persons. The
general rule rests upon the fact that the dam has more care over the
young than the sire, while it is departed from in the case of swans,
because the male bird shares the care with the female. In
some cases the ownership is divided between a temporary owner, such as
a bailee for hire, and an ultimate owner, when' the young are born. In
this case they belong to the hirer.
Personal
property falls plainly within the jurisdiction of equity, since the
common-law courts could grant no relief in this class of
cases. All the needed power was at hand in the courts
of equity, since they could take an accounting, ascertain all the
facts, have a reference to a master, provide for an equality of
division, protect the rights of infants and married women, order a sale
if necessary for division, and direct the parties to make all requisite
assignments and transfers.
PART III.
TITLE TO PERSONAL PROPERTY.
Thus far it has been the object to consider the ownership of personal
property, the various interests that may be acquired in it, and the
qualifications imposed upon ownership by general rules of
law. It still remains to consider how property may be
acquired. This inquiry involves the title to property.
There are various modes of acquiring title to personal property.
Some writers treat these simply by way of enumeration.
Others, for example Chancellor Kent, arrange them under principal
divisions, with subordinate titles. His method leads to three principal
divisions, — title by original acquisition, by act of the law, and by
act of the parties. A similar arrangement will be adopted
here. One class embraces things which are obtained by the
claimant himself through his own act. The title is not
derivative from others, but originates with him. The plainest case of
this kind is mental origination. This embraces the
authorship of a literary work, or the production of a picture or
statue. Other instances are the finding of property on land
or sea, capturing it in time of war. So property already
owned may receive additions to its value which, by being incorporated
with it, become in law a part of it. From this fact springs
a form of title termed title by "accession." So goods
belonging to different owners may be commingled in such a way that one
gains the title to the whole. This leads to a special form
of title, that is, by " confusion." Finally, one may take
materials belonging to mankind in common, and so appropriate them to
his own use as to become owner, particularly where he has added labor
to them. This may be termed title by "production." These
various modes of acquiring title will now be considered.
CHAPTER I.
TITLE BY ORIGINAL ACQUISITION.
DIVISION I. — Title by Capture.
There are two modes of acquiring property in this way, one upon land,
and the other upon water. The first is called booty, and
the second, prize.
Section I. Booty. — There
is a practical distinction of much consequence between booty and
prize. As to the latter, a court of admiralty has, by the
regular course of law, jurisdiction to determine its status, that is,
whether it is lawful prize or not. This is not so with
booty. The right to that does not depend upon a legal
adjudication, but upon undisturbed possession by the captor for a
reasonable time. This defect in law is remedied in England
by statute, conferring upon the admiralty court jurisdiction in this
class of cases. The right to take possession and hold
captured property is based upon the right of conquest.
Section II.
Prize. — This term is applied to such property as is taken at sea by
the right of conquest in time of war, whether from an opposing
belligerent, or from a neutral violating the law of nations in respect
to war. In this class of cases, it is the general rule that
the property should be brought for condemnation into a port belonging
to the captor. Still, under peculiar circumstances,
condemnation may take place, though the captured property is in a
neutral port, and it may be sold there. Such a case must be
treated as an exception, and cannot be cited as a precedent.
It is, perhaps, a correct distinction that undisturbed possession by a
captor of a captured ship gives him a title de facto., while the
condemnation by a prize court gives the title de jure.
The proceeding is in rem, or against the property itself.
The decision of a prize court having jurisdiction so far fixes the
status of the property that the title passes to the captor.
This is recognized in courts of other countries, including those of the
country where the captured property originally belonged.
Redress, if the decision be erroneous, can only be obtained by
diplomacy ; and if that fail, by war. The ground of this
rule is that the legal proceeding is against the thing
captured. Its object is to establish the status or
ownership of the thing, and the judgment of the court fixes or
establishes such ownership. It is not intended to develop
the details of prize law, but only to point out the relation of the
topic to the title to personal property.
AMERICAN LAW AND PROCEDURE
VOLUME II.
PREPARED UNDER THE EDITORIAL SUPERVISION OF
JAMES PARKER HALL. A. B.
LL. B.
Dean of the University of Chicago Law School
COPYRIGHT 1910
BY
LA SALLE EXTENSION UNIVERSITY
~~~~~~~~~~
TORTS
by
GEORGE LUTHER CLARK
Professor of Law, University of Michigan
CHAPTER 1
§1. Definition of a tort. The word "tort" has been borrowed
from the French; it means
literally a wrong (1). In its legal meaning, however, the term is not
used to include everything
which the law treats as a wrong. For example, a crime or breach of
contract is a legal wrong,
but they are both to be distinguished from a torl The most important
rights protected by the
law of torts are those of personal security, of property, of
reputation, and of social and
business relations.
(1) The French word "tort" was In was turn derived
from the Latin "torquere," meanlng to twist or bend.
§7. Difference between intent, negligence, and accident. If
A is driving on the highway and
drives over B, he may do this either intentionally, negligently, or
accidentally. That is, he may
desire to run over B (intent), if he does not desire it he may not use
the proper amount of care
not to run over him (negligence), and if he does not desire it and
drives carefully it is then
called an accident. Intent is thus seen to be a state of mind,
negligence is a kind of behavior,
while accident, as the word is often used in a legal sense, is the
negation of both intent and
negligence. As will be seen later, accident is generally a defense
unless the defendant was
engaged at the time in an unlawful or an extra-hazardous act. The torts
which are first
discussed, trespass, conversion, and deceit, are generally intentional,
except trespass which is
frequently the result of carelessness. After these, are discussed in
order the subjects of
negligence and liability for accident.
§8. Intent distinguished from motive. The difference
between intent and motive is briefly
this: a defendant acts intentionally when he desires a particular
result, without reference to
the reason for sum desire. Motive, on the other hand, is the reason why
the defendant
desires the result. Motive is material only in those torts discussed in
the later
chapters--defamation, malicious prosecution, and malicious interference
with business and
social relations.
THE LAW OF TORTS
In General (individual's rights)
1. right to be free from
bodily harm
2. right to enjoy a good
reputation
3. right to conduct business
with out wrongful interference
4. right to have property
free from interference
A Tort is interference with another's right by:
1. intent
2.
negligence
3. strict liability
The injured party sues the defendant or tort feasor.
1. Brought in civil court
2. Seek damages
3. Not necessarily a crime
4. Standard – preponderance
of the evidence (i.e. more likely than not)
Intentional Torts
1. Assault – threaten to
strike or harm resulting in fear.
2. Battery – unlawful,
unprivileged touching
3. Trespass – wrongful
injury or interference with another's property
4. Nuisance – anything that
interferes with another's enjoyment of property
5. Interference with contract
6. Deceit
7. Conversion
8. False
imprisonment
9. Defamation
10. Invasion of privacy
11. Misuse of legal procedure
12. Infliction of emotional distress
The Elements of an
Intentional Tort
1. An intentional tort.
2. An injury.
3. Tort was the proximate
cause of injury.
4. Injury caused damages.
The Intentional Torts
Assault
Threatening to strike or harm
with a weapon or physical movement, resulting in fear.
Battery
Unlawful, unprivileged touching
of another person.
Trespass
Wrongful injury or interference
with the property of another.
Nuisance
Anything that interferes with the
enjoyment of life or property.
Interference with contractual relations
Intentionally causing one person
not to enter or to break a contract with another.
Deceit
False statement or deceptive
practice done with intent to injure another.
Conversion
Unauthorized taking or borrowing of personal
property of another for the use of the taker.
False imprisonment
Unlawful restraint of a person,
whether in prison or otherwise.
Defamation
Wrongful act of injuring
another's reputation by making false statements.
Invasion of privacy
Interference with person's right
to be lef alone.
Misuse of legal procedure.
Bringing of legal action with
malice and without probable cause.
Infliction of emotional distress
Intentionally or recklessly
causing emotional or mental suffering to others.
NEGLIGENCE
Most common tort
1. Duty of Care – a
reasonable responsibility to act or not to act
2. Breach of Duty – the reasonable person
test. (not equal to logical, normal or average)
3. Proximate Cause – without breach the result
would not have occurred. (not equal to actual cause)
4. Actual harm – (i.e.
physical injury, property damage)
5. Measurable Damages- a
financial loss ( may include pain and suffering)
Defenses to Negligence
1. Contributory Negligence – If plaintiff's own
negligence helped cause the injuries, then the plaintiff loses the
lawsuit.
2. Comparative Negligence – (Adopted by most
states) Plaintiff's recovery is reduced by the percent of his or
her negligence.
Assumption
of Risk – If defendant can show that the plaintiff knew of the risk and
still took the chance of being injured, may claim this defense to bar
plaintiff's recovery.
The third tort
Strict Liability
The doctrine of strict liability
Ø Applies to ultra-hazardous activities that
involve a great risk to people and property.
Ø The risk is so significant
that amount of care will eliminate that risk.
Ø (i.e. wild animals,
explosives, highly flammable liquids)
Also, applies to product liability –
Ø cases in which people are
injured from defects in products.
Ø The firm that manufactures
a product is liable.
Ø regardless of the fault for injuries to users
of the product if a defect in one of those machines.
Ø Does not apply if company
does not actively engage in the sale of that good.
Wrongful death statutes – preserve the rights of third parties affected
by the death of a person to bring a lawsuit.
Punitive
damages relate to gross negligence and reckless disregard goes beyond
compensation and allows the plaintiff to attack company profits.

WASHINGTON, D.C. – Three out of four tort cases filed in the nation's
75 most populous counties never reached the courtroom because they were
settled out of court, according to a Department of Justice study
released today. Only 3 percent went to trial, with the plaintiff
winning about half the time.
The study of 378,000 state tort cases (about half of all tort suits
completed from July 1, 1991, through June 30, 1992) found that
more than 75 percent involved automobile accidents or property
liability claims. Medical malpractice, product liability and
toxic substance cases accounted for 10 percent. Torts are wrongful
acts--not including contract disputes--that result in injury to
another's person, property or reputation and for which the injured
party is entitled to compensation.
The average tort case took a little more than 19 months to
conclude. In one-quarter of the cases, the defendant did not file
an answer, and most of these uncontested cases ended in settlement
agreements. Seven percent of medical malpractice claims were
concluded by a trial, and in these the defendants won three out of four
cases.
Automobile tort cases
primarily involved individuals suing individuals. Medical
malpractice cases were mostly individuals against hospitals.
Toxic substance and other product liability cases most often involved
individuals filing against businesses.
The types of tort cases filed in the state courts of general
jurisdiction in the nation's 75 most populous counties included:
Auto . . . . . .
. . . 60 percent
Property . . . . . . . . .17
Other negligence . . . . . 6
Medical malpractice . . . 5
Product liability . . . . 3
Intentional injury . . . . 3
Non-medical malpractice . 2
Toxic substance . . . . . 2
Slander and libel . . . . 1
Unknown . . . . . . . . . 1
In the 29 states in which the National Center for State Courts analyzed
1993 data, there were almost 6 million civil cases, which fell into the
following types:
Domestic relations . . . . 41
percent
Small claims . . . . . . . 12
Contracts . . . . . . . . 11
Torts . . . . . . . . . . 10
Estates . . . . . . . . . 10
Real property rights . . . 7
Other . . . . . . . . .
. 5
Mental health . . . . .
. 2
Civil appeals . . . . .
. 2
The Center also said the number of tort
filings remained relatively stable from 1986 through 1993.
Tort trial cases terminated in U.S. district courts, 1996-1997
Jury and Bench cases terminated
3,023
Plaintiff winners
1,249
Number of monetary awards to plaintiff
1,073
Median Award
$141,000
Of
the 96,284 tort cases that were terminated in U.S. district courts
during fiscal years 1996 and 1997, 3,023 or 3% were decided by a
completed jury or bench trial.
* Motor
vehicle claims comprised 19.4% of tort trial cases, product liability
15.9%, and medical malpractice 7.4%.
* Diversity
of citizenship (cases that involve citizens from different States) was
the reason why Federal rather State Courts handled 72% of tort trial
cases, 15.6% involved a Federal question and 12.3% involved the U.S.
Government as a plaintiff (0.2%) or a defendant (12.1%).
* A jury decided 75% of tort cases brought to trial.
* Plaintiffs won in 1,249 or 45% of the tort cases
decided by trial verdict.
* In 86% of the tort trial cases in which the plaintiffs won, the jury
or court awarded damages. The median award was $141,000.
* In 10% of the tort trial cases with a plaintiff winner, damages
awarded were over $1 million and in 8% of the cases, awards exceeded
$10 million.
* The median case processing time
for all tort cases from filing to termination exclusive of time on
appeal was 17.3 months.
http://facweb.eths.k12.il.us/feeleyd/lawnotes/tortnotes.htm
BLACK'S LAW DICTIONARY 1st Ed., 1891 BLACK'S LAW DICTIONARY 4th Ed., 1951 BOUVIER'S LAW DICTIONARY 1856
